Essay
No, it is not necessary. This categorical definition of free will is overly strong, and would require that agents be able to act against their interests. In this essay, I will first investigate our motivations for producing an analysis of free will at all, and then explore the categorical, conditional, and actual-sequence views, concluding that the actual-sequence account is the definition that we ought to use.
The question above invites a discussion about what we mean by the word
“freely”. We cannot test empirically whether a definition is correct, as
changing the concept that a particular string of characters refers to
would not lead us to different, falsifiable predictions about reality.
Definitions allow us to distinguish between concepts, but these
distinctions are not mind-independent features of the world
(
Putnam 1988, 114
Why argue over the meaning of “freely” at all? Justifications are often given in terms of importance for morality (Watson 1982, 8-11):
P1: S’s freely doing φ is a necessary condition for S to be morally responsible for φ.
P2: S’s moral responsibility for φ is a necessary condition for S to be a legitimate object of praise or blame for φ.
C: Each of the necessary conditions for S doing φ freely is individually required for S to be legitimately praised or blamed for φ.
If this argument is sound (for it is valid via modus ponens), then an
analysis of freedom would help with deliberations over whether or not to
praise or blame others for their actions. However, P2 is not
necessarily true. An act-utilitarian would point out that the actions of
praising and blaming are instrumental towards maximising utility (Smart
1993, 49-50): if it happens that utility is maximised when S is
reproached for an action they are not morally responsible for, then so
be it. Therefore, at least insofar as
applications to morality are concerned, the
following analysis of freedom is
useful
There is an attractive simplicity to the proposition that, for an action
φ to have been done freely, it must have been possible (without a change
in circumstances) to have not-φed.1 An
immediate
problem
Relaxing the requirement for S to have φed freely to “if S had wanted to not-φ, S would have not-φed” is one natural response to the argument from reasons (Wolf 1980, 154). By no longer requiring that the circumstances of the action remain the same, this conditional definition avoids the awkward implication that S must be able to act in opposition to their interests, and fits with our intuition that freedom is about being able to do what you want. However, there are several issues with the conditional approach. First, a practical one: the conditional presented is a counterfactual. This poses problems for evaluating its truth-value when trying to ascertain whether a particular action φ was done freely by S. One could appeal to the “closest possible world” in which S wanted to not-φ, and try and establish whether S would have φed in it, but that presupposes both that (a) one has some objective metric to judge the closeness of possible worlds, and (b) one is able to determine what happens in a hypothetical world we are not in. Since we want an analysis of freedom to answer other questions (such as around moral responsibility), it is unhelpful to have a definition that cannot be evaluated.
Moreover, the conditional account does not fit with our intuitions about freedom. Take the following example, based loosely on McKenna and Coates (2023):
Suppose Victoria is a smoking addict. A friend offers her a cigarette. Victoria wants it very much and starts to smoke.
If Victoria had wanted to not smoke, then she would not have done so.
But it seems strange to say that Victoria freely chose to smoke: our
intuition is that she had no choice but to. These
inconsistencies between the conditional view and our intuitions
Suppose Scarlett has implanted a chip into Jones’s brain which lets her manipulate him. She hopes Jones will steal some money and monitors him, ready to switch on the chip at the first sign that he doesn’t wish to steal the money. Jones does decide to steal, so the chip remains inactivated.
Since Jones could not have failed to steal the money if he wanted to,
the conditional account rules that he did not freely do so in this case.
Yet our intuitions lead us to conclude that, since Scarlett did not
actually intervene to manipulate him, Jones stole the money freely. We
should,
therefore
Actual-sequence accounts – arguing that in order for S to have φed freely, S’s φing must have been caused by a desire to φ – provide an elegant solution to FSCs. Jones’s inability to not steal is irrelevant to the actual-sequence account’s intuitive judgement that he stole freely (Frankfurt 1969, 837).
In cases like Victoria’s, the actual-sequence might appear to give the wrong verdict: Victoria’s desire to smoke caused her to do so, but it was not free. In particular, we might think that Victoria wishes that she were not addicted to cigarettes, and therefore does not want to want to smoke (a second-order desire). However, trying to overcome this failure by explicitly specifying that “S’s φing is free only if it is caused by a desire S desires to have” would be vulnerable to another counterexample, this time referencing conflicting third-order desires (and so on with higher-order desires).
We can successfully refine the actual-sequence account to address this entire class of objections by defining S’s φing as free only if, after reflection, both (a) such that S endorses an n^th^-order desire which causes S’s φing; and (b) such that S’s m^th^-order desire conflicts with that n^th^-order desire (Frankfurt 1987, 164). In Victoria’s case, condition (b) is not met, since her second-order desire straightforwardly conflicts with the first-order one. More generally, this analysis fits neatly with our intuitions that a person does something freely only if they wholeheartedly wish to do it, but also that superficially forced actions we willingly pre-commit to2 can still be said to be free.
In light of these arguments, I conclude that the ability to have not-φed
is not necessary in order to have φed freely – possessing the
ability to do other than φ in the same circumstances would in fact be at
odds with having agency at all. Whilst the conditional view is an
improvement, it fails to deliver the correct judgements in instances of
psychological compulsion or FSCs. As I have argued,
the actual-sequence account provides the best analysis
References
Frankfurt, H., 1969, “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility”, The Journal of Philosophy, 66(23), 829–839.
———, 1987, “Identification and Wholeheartedness,” in Frankfurt, H., 1988, Philosophical Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McKenna, Michael and Coates, D. Justin, “Compatibilism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.)
Putnam, H., 1988, Representation and Reality, Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press.
Smart, J.J.C., 1993, “An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics”, in Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Watson, G., 1982, “Introduction”, in Watson, G., (ed.), 1982, Free Will, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wolf, S., 1980, Asymmetrical Freedom, The Journal of Philosophy, 77(3), 151–166.
-
I will interpret “circumstances” broadly: the conjunction , where is the conjunction of all physical laws, and is the state of the universe at the point that φ is performed (Inwagen 1975, 191). We can say that an event is “possible” just in case it is not impossible, i.e. , where is the “necessary” operator. To put it another way, the conjunction must not be a contradiction. ↩︎
-
For example, I ask a friend to make me exercise tomorrow, because I know I will lack motivation, but will still want to want to exercise. ↩︎